"

Preface

Donald V. Stump

The editors of this book originally conceived the idea of a festschrift for John Crossett after reminiscing one evening about how much he had given to us, his former students, and how little we had repaid him. At that time, we hoped to be able to hand him a copy of this book on his sixtieth birthday and, by that token of our affection and admiration, to make him some small return for the endless effort he lav­ished on us, both during and after the time we were his perverse and obstreperous students.

We were too slow; he is now dead. Instead of being a gift for him, this volume has become a memorial to him. It is, however, not his only nor his best memorial. All of us who were influenced by his peculiar combination of selfless dedication to truth and warm care for others are his true memorial. In the best of our work and character, his spirit lives on.

In planning the book, we decided to look for a unifying theme that would honor Crossett and also elicit fruitful new studies from his former students and colleagues. The classical concept of hamartia seemed an ideal choice for both purposes. Crossett had worked out an extraordinarily useful definition of hamartia as double-mindedness (a definition explained at length by James A. Arieti in the first essay of the volume). With this idea, Crossett had helped to elucidate the genre of tragedy as it was practiced in a variety of cultural settings. At the time of his death, he had nearly completed his share of the commentary and translation for a new edition of Aristotle’s Poetics, which he was preparing jointly with Hippocrates G. Apostle. He had also written extensive research notes and essays on the function of hamartia in the work of dramatists as diverse as Sophocles, Shakespeare, and Anouilh, and he had examined the notion of tragedy evident in the non-dramatic works of poets such as Geoffrey Chaucer and Edmund Spenser. He had also extended his research on the term to include its role in ethical and theological contexts. In particular, he had carried out extensive philological and theological studies of the New Testament in order to trace the shift in meaning from “error” in older Greek writings to “sin” in Christian documents.

Unfortunately, most of Crossett’s research on hamartia survives only in rough draft and will never see print. Therefore, it seems all the more appropriate for us to extend the investigation here, knowing that no other topic could have pleased him more. As we discovered when we first sent out letters of inquiry to potential contributors, the concept is also germane to the scholarship of many of his col­ leagues and former students. Like logos and eros, hamartia has had a profound and pervasive influence on Western culture. It has played a part in areas as diverse as Greek history and Renaissance drama, Hellenistic theology and Victorian fiction. Because of its significance in Greek philosophy and literary criticism, the term has been most influen­ tial in those subsequent ages which self-consciously returned to the standards of antiquity, most notably the Renaissance and the eighteenth century. But even in the Middle Ages, when the Greek classics were little known, and in the nineteenth century, when many writers were turning away from the neo-classicism of the preceding century, the notion of hamartia often proves useful in interpreting works of philosophy and literature.

Nearly half the essays in this volume discuss hamartia in connection with Greek antiquity. James A. Arieti investigates its importance as the primary unifying theme in the work of the Greek historian Herodotus. Norman Kretzmann considers the term in its New Testament definition and examines the old problem cogently posed by Plato in the Euthyphro: Does God disapprove of a thing because it is bad, or is a thing bad because because God disapproves of it? Carol Lindsay Begley and Janet Smith both investigate hamartia as a threat to rational thought and discourse—an abrogation of the all-important Greek commitment to logos. Begley interprets Euripides’s Hippolytus as a play about errors of the tongue, and Smith discusses the importance of the idea of tragic misologia in the dialogues of Plato, particularly in the Phaedo. Hippocrates G. Apostle brings together in one essay a variety of Aristotelian distinctions between the various forms of error, and Lloyd Gerson discusses the Old Stoic paradox “All errors are equal,” pointing out the psychological and ethical assumptions that underlie it and make it alien to the philosophy of Plato and the Middle Stoa.

The next essay in the book considers the concept of error in medieval theology. Steven Baldner examines Aquinas’s solution to a difficult epistemological problem: how may a theologian argue from the revealed truth of Scripture to refute the errors of those who may not accept key articles of the Christian faith?

The final group of essays in the book explores the concept of error in English literature from the fourteenth to the nineteenth centuries. James S. Cutsinger examines the rad­ical shift in the notions of truth and error that accompany the advent of Romanticism, particularly in the works of Col­eridge.The other four essays all explore the applicability of Aristotle’s theory of tragedy to the work of English authors. Carolynn Van Dyke argues that, even though medieval Christian notions of error are based on different ethical assumptions from those of the ancient Greeks, Aris­totle’s theory of tragedy is universal and may be adapted to illuminate works such as Chaucer’s Troi/us and Criseyde and the anonymous poem Sir Gawain and the Green Knight. S. P. Zitner and Donald V. Stump both examine the problem of applying Aristotle to Shakespeare. Zitner argues that Aristotelian criticism was “in the air” in Elizabethan England and that each of Shakespeare’s major tragedies involves a hamartia. Zitner then provides a reading of Hamlet exam­ining the importance of error in the design of the play. Stump seeks to supply what scholars have long been unable to provide: a set of intermediaries from whom Shakespeare could have learned the structure of the ancient Greek hamartia-play. Finally, Elizabeth Holtze discusses George Eliot’s adaptation of Aristotle’s theory to the demands of the novel, pointing out the influence of Greek tragedy upon var­ious plot lines in Adam Bede.

All the essays in the volume are, in one way or another, indebted to John Crossett’s original research on the concept of hamartia, and the range of subjects that they represent suggests something about the great breadth of his own interests and the richness of-his learning. If the book has shortcomings, they should be attributed only to the sad fact that he died before he knew of its existence. Had he lived to see the manuscript before its publication, we would undoubtedly have made a better book, for he would have been our sternest critic.

Donald V. Stump